Foreword |
|
ix | |
|
Preface |
|
xi | |
Acknowledgements |
|
xviii | |
|
Day 1 Roe v. Wade and Other Legal Concerns |
|
|
1 | (25) |
|
(a) Docs the Bible prohibit abortions? |
|
|
2 | (1) |
|
(b) The thalidomide scare |
|
|
3 | (1) |
|
(c) Does Roe v. Wade legalize abortion on demand? |
|
|
4 | (2) |
|
(d) Roe v. Wade does not legalize abortion on demand |
|
|
6 | (1) |
|
(e) What's included in the right to privacy? |
|
|
7 | (1) |
|
(f) Planned Parenthood v. Casey asserts viability as the point where abortion can be restricted |
|
|
8 | (1) |
|
(g) Many states do restrict abortion access at some point in pregnancy |
|
|
9 | (1) |
|
(h) New York's Reproductive Health Act. |
|
|
9 | (1) |
|
(i) Doe v. Bolton, and how to define maternal health |
|
|
10 | (1) |
|
(j) Making abortions illegal won't stop them |
|
|
11 | (1) |
|
(k) The effectiveness of laws prohibiting abortion |
|
|
12 | (1) |
|
(l) Women sentenced to prison over a miscarriage and the case of Savita Halappanavar |
|
|
12 | (1) |
|
(m) The role of contraception in reducing abortion rates |
|
|
13 | (1) |
|
(n) The role of sex education in reducing abortion rates |
|
|
13 | (1) |
|
(o) Do our tax dollars fund abortion? |
|
|
14 | (1) |
|
(p) Personhood Amendments |
|
|
15 | (1) |
|
(q) Embryos and fertility treatments |
|
|
16 | (1) |
|
(r) Killing abortion doctors |
|
|
17 | (1) |
|
(s) Does abortion harm women? |
|
|
18 | (8) |
|
Day 2 Abortions as Murder, Fetal Personhood, and Arguments from Potential |
|
|
26 | (25) |
|
(a) Viability and quickening as times when abortion becomes murder |
|
|
26 | (1) |
|
(b) Abortion kills an innocent child |
|
|
27 | (1) |
|
(c) Can "innocence" apply to embryos? |
|
|
28 | (1) |
|
(d) Is killing all human life wrong? |
|
|
29 | (1) |
|
|
30 | (1) |
|
(f) Is genetic humanity sufficient for personhood? |
|
|
30 | (1) |
|
(g) The cognitive traits of personhood |
|
|
30 | (1) |
|
(h) Persons who are not genetically human |
|
|
31 | (1) |
|
(i) Genetic humans who are not persons |
|
|
32 | (1) |
|
(j) Embryos and fetuses lack all the mental traits of personhood |
|
|
33 | (1) |
|
(k) The relationship between rights and desires |
|
|
34 | (1) |
|
(l) Do infants have a right to life? |
|
|
35 | (1) |
|
(m) The argument from potential |
|
|
36 | (1) |
|
(n) What does "potential" mean? |
|
|
36 | (4) |
|
(o) Do potential persons have the same rights as actual persons? |
|
|
40 | (2) |
|
(p) The right to life protects persons from harm |
|
|
42 | (1) |
|
(q) Sentience as a prerequisite for being able to be harmed |
|
|
42 | (1) |
|
(r) Harm as the setting back of interests |
|
|
43 | (1) |
|
(s) Must you be sentient in order to have interests? |
|
|
44 | (1) |
|
(t) When do fetuses become sentient? |
|
|
45 | (6) |
|
Day 3 Fetal "Future-Like-Ours" Arguments, and Considerations of Personal Identity |
|
|
51 | (27) |
|
(a) Sanctity of life arguments |
|
|
51 | (2) |
|
(b) Sanctity of life arguments and euthanasia |
|
|
53 | (2) |
|
(c) Abortion and religious diversity |
|
|
55 | (1) |
|
(d) Future-like-ours arguments |
|
|
56 | (2) |
|
(e) Future-like-ours arguments, contraception, and arguments from potential |
|
|
58 | (1) |
|
(f) Alternative accounts of the wrongness of killing |
|
|
59 | (3) |
|
(g) Do fetuses have futures of value? |
|
|
62 | (1) |
|
(h) Is the fetus the same being that will later enjoy a future? |
|
|
63 | (2) |
|
(i) A fertilized egg is not an individual human being |
|
|
65 | (1) |
|
(j) Personal identity consists in the persistence of a human organism |
|
|
65 | (1) |
|
(k) Personal identity consists in the continuation of mental contents |
|
|
66 | (1) |
|
(l) Personal identity consists in the continuation of a conscious mind |
|
|
67 | (3) |
|
(m) Does death harm a fetus to the same degree as it harms a person? |
|
|
70 | (8) |
|
Day 4 The Bodily Autonomy Argument |
|
|
78 | (30) |
|
(a) Abortion and the security persons |
|
|
78 | (1) |
|
(b) Is the right to life a positive right? |
|
|
79 | (3) |
|
(c) The violinist example |
|
|
82 | (1) |
|
(d) Is the violinist example too weird? |
|
|
83 | (2) |
|
(e) The violinist example's relevance to abortion |
|
|
85 | (3) |
|
(f) Kant's principle of humanity and its relation to pregnancy and abortion |
|
|
88 | (3) |
|
(g) The violinist example as analogous to rape |
|
|
91 | (1) |
|
(h) The responsibility objection |
|
|
91 | (3) |
|
(i) The tacit consent objection |
|
|
94 | (2) |
|
(j) The special relationship objection |
|
|
96 | (2) |
|
(k) The killing vs. letting die distinction |
|
|
98 | (2) |
|
(l) Restricting abortion after viability |
|
|
100 | (2) |
|
(m) Can we compel using someone's body to save another? |
|
|
102 | (1) |
|
(n) The compensation objection |
|
|
103 | (5) |
|
Day 5 Abortion in Hard Cases |
|
|
108 | (31) |
|
(a) Pro-choice and feminism |
|
|
109 | (1) |
|
(b) Early feminism and pro-life advocacy |
|
|
109 | (1) |
|
(c) Does abortion allow for the sexual exploitation of women? |
|
|
110 | (1) |
|
(d) Abortion and pro-family support policies |
|
|
110 | (1) |
|
(e) Areas where pro-choice and pro-life feminists agree |
|
|
111 | (2) |
|
(f) Abortion due to Sex-selection |
|
|
113 | (2) |
|
(g) Virtue theory and abortion |
|
|
115 | (3) |
|
|
118 | (1) |
|
(i) Abortion for non-viable pregnancies |
|
|
119 | (2) |
|
(j) Abortion due to fetal disabilities |
|
|
121 | (1) |
|
(k) Is there a duty to have the "best" child? |
|
|
122 | (1) |
|
(l) Subjective stories of families with disabled children |
|
|
122 | (1) |
|
(m) The exprcssivist argument against selective abortion |
|
|
123 | (1) |
|
(n) The parental attitude argument against selective abortion |
|
|
124 | (1) |
|
|
125 | (1) |
|
|
126 | (3) |
|
(q) Men and grief over abortion |
|
|
129 | (1) |
|
(r) Can a man force a woman to gestate? |
|
|
129 | (1) |
|
(s) Abortion in cases of rape |
|
|
130 | (3) |
|
|
133 | (6) |
Annotated Bibliography |
|
139 | (22) |
Index |
|
161 | |