Preface |
|
xi | |
Acknowledgments |
|
xiii | |
|
1 Introduction and Overview |
|
|
1 | (11) |
|
2 What Is War - and Can a Lone Individual Wage One? |
|
|
12 | (19) |
|
2.1 Defining War - What Is It Good For? |
|
|
12 | (2) |
|
2.2 War as Event and War as Action |
|
|
14 | (1) |
|
|
15 | (3) |
|
|
18 | (2) |
|
|
20 | (5) |
|
2.6 A Comparison with Some Other Definitions |
|
|
25 | (6) |
|
3 Jus ad Bellum: Justifying the Use of War |
|
|
31 | (84) |
|
|
32 | (19) |
|
3.1.1 Traditional Just War Theory and Legitimate Authority |
|
|
33 | (3) |
|
3.1.2 The Spurious "Priority" of Legitimate Authority |
|
|
36 | (6) |
|
3.1.3 The Consequentialist Argument for Legitimate Authority: The Specter of Chaos and Anarchy |
|
|
42 | (4) |
|
3.1.4 Other Arguments for Legitimate Authority or "Authorization"? |
|
|
46 | (4) |
|
|
50 | (1) |
|
3.2 Just Cause and "Right Intention" |
|
|
51 | (40) |
|
3.2.1 Just Cause, Retribution, and the Continuous Application of Jus ad Bellum |
|
|
51 | (1) |
|
3.2.1.1 The Formal Question: What Kind of Thing Is a "Just Cause" for War? |
|
|
52 | (9) |
|
3.2.1.2 The General Substantive Question: "Which Causes Are Just?" or "Under What Conditions Is There a Just Cause?" |
|
|
61 | (7) |
|
3.2.1.3 The Question of Timing: Does the "Just Cause" Criterion Only Apply to the Initiation of a War or Also to Its Continuation? |
|
|
68 | (5) |
|
3.2.2 Right Intention? The Subjective Element of a Justified War |
|
|
73 | (3) |
|
3.2.2.1 The Indispensability of "Right Intention" in the Form of a Knowledge Requirement |
|
|
76 | (5) |
|
3.2.2.2 Objections to the Previous Argument |
|
|
81 | (6) |
|
3.2.2.3 The Mere Knowledge Requirement Is also Sufficient |
|
|
87 | (1) |
|
3.2.3 Just Cause and the Subjective Element: Conclusions and Practical Consequences |
|
|
88 | (3) |
|
3.3 Proportionality (Again): The Subcriteria of Prospects of Success and Last Resort |
|
|
91 | (7) |
|
3.3.1 Prospects of Success |
|
|
91 | (4) |
|
|
95 | (3) |
|
|
98 | (17) |
|
4 Jus in hello: Justifying the Use of Force in War |
|
|
115 | (178) |
|
4.1 Ordinary Morality and Jus in Bello: Correcting "Revisionist" Misrepresentations of Domestic Peacetime Morality and Its Implications for War |
|
|
115 | (99) |
|
4.1.1 McMahan's "Responsibility Account" of "Liability to Defensive Force" as a Non-Starter |
|
|
124 | (5) |
|
4.1.2 Rodin on Self-Defense and the "Myth" of National Self-Defense: A Refutation |
|
|
129 | (1) |
|
4.1.2.1 Necessity and the "Duty to Retreat" |
|
|
130 | (3) |
|
4.1.2.2 Proportionality in Self-Defense |
|
|
133 | (3) |
|
4.1.2.3 Wide Proportionality and Imposing the Risk of Death on People One Defends |
|
|
136 | (7) |
|
4.1.2.4 Rodin on Just War Theory, International Law, and "Copernican Moments" |
|
|
143 | (3) |
|
4.1.2.5 War as Law Enforcement and Punishment: The Incoherence of Rodin's Account |
|
|
146 | (2) |
|
|
148 | (1) |
|
4.1.3 Self-Defense Redeemed: The Common Understanding of the Self-Defense Justification |
|
|
148 | (3) |
|
4.1.4 Beyond Self-Defense: The Defensive and the Aggressive Emergency Justification |
|
|
151 | (5) |
|
4.1.5 Self-Defense vs. Justifying Emergency: Implications for Participating in War |
|
|
156 | (2) |
|
4.1.5.1 Equality and Inequality in War: Background and Conceptual Clarifications |
|
|
158 | (2) |
|
4.1.5.2 The Dubious Argument for the Two Inequality Doctrines |
|
|
160 | (3) |
|
4.1.5.3 Proportionality and Special Responsibilities or Prerogatives |
|
|
163 | (7) |
|
4.1.5.4 In Which Wars May Soldiers Participate? |
|
|
170 | (4) |
|
4.1.6 The Deceptive Allure of the "Revisionist" Inequality of Combatants Doctrine: On Imagined Innovations, Question-Begging Definitions, and Dogmatic Insistence |
|
|
174 | (1) |
|
4.1.6.1 The Moral Inequality Thesis in History: Imagined and Real Orthodoxies |
|
|
175 | (5) |
|
4.1.6.2 The Revisionist Formulation of the Inequality Thesis: Tautologies and Question-Begging |
|
|
180 | (2) |
|
4.1.6.3 The Inequality Thesis as Sustained by the "Justification Defeats Liability" Doctrine: On Ad Hoccery and Dogmatism |
|
|
182 | (10) |
|
4.1.7 The Doctrine of Double Effect (and Related Principles) |
|
|
192 | (2) |
|
4.1.7.1 Preliminaries: A Non-Absolutist Formulation of the Doctrine of Double Effect and First Doubts about Its Credibility |
|
|
194 | (3) |
|
4.1.7.2 A Rigged Comparison: The Terror Bomber/Tactical Bomber Example |
|
|
197 | (10) |
|
4.1.7.3 The Equally Rigged Trolley Examples - and a Universal Counter-Example |
|
|
207 | (4) |
|
4.1.7.4 A Convenient Distraction: The "Sophisticated Bomber" |
|
|
211 | (2) |
|
|
213 | (1) |
|
4.2 War, Law, and Reciprocity: Devising the Moral Rules of War |
|
|
214 | (79) |
|
4.2.1 Moral Fundamentalism vs. Constitutivism: The Relation between Widely Accepted Laws and the Ethics of War |
|
|
215 | (1) |
|
4.2.1.1 Moral Fundamentalism and McMahan's Incoherent Account of the Relation between the "Deep Morality" and the Laws of War |
|
|
216 | (6) |
|
4.2.1.2 Two Kinds of "Reductivism" |
|
|
222 | (3) |
|
4.2.1.3 On Haque's "Service View" of the Laws of War - A Brief Critique |
|
|
225 | (6) |
|
4.2.1.4 Examples against Moral Fundamentalism: Reciprocity and the Morally Constitutive Force of Widely Accepted Conventions |
|
|
231 | (5) |
|
4.2.1.5 Lessons for War, Part I: The Variable Moral Scopes and Limits of Necessity and Proportionality in War |
|
|
236 | (5) |
|
4.2.1.6 Lessons for War, Part II: Reciprocity, Conventions, and the Moral Equality of Combatants |
|
|
241 | (3) |
|
4.2.1.7 Lessons for War, Part III: The Principle of Distinction |
|
|
244 | (3) |
|
4.2.1.8 A Further Reason Why Moral Fundamentalism Is Mistaken: The Moral Significance of Publicly Authorized Functions and Roles |
|
|
247 | (1) |
|
|
248 | (2) |
|
4.2.2 Against Benbaji's and Statman's "Contractarianism" |
|
|
250 | (43) |
Concluding Remarks |
|
293 | (8) |
References |
|
301 | (16) |
Index |
|
317 | |