Contributors |
|
xvii | |
Introduction Why philosophers of psychiatry should care about evolutionary theory |
|
1 | (32) |
|
|
|
1.1 Psychiatric Darwinism versus Darwinian psychiatry |
|
|
3 | (3) |
|
1.2 Explaining the evolution of mental disorders |
|
|
6 | (4) |
|
1.3 Sociobiology, evolutionary psychology, evolutionary psychiatry: philosophical criticism |
|
|
10 | (9) |
|
1.4 Evolution, dysfunction, and mental disorders |
|
|
19 | (4) |
|
1.5 Das kranke Tier: evolution, psychopathology, and human nature |
|
|
23 | (4) |
|
|
27 | (6) |
|
|
27 | (6) |
|
Part 1 Evolutionary psychiatry and its critics |
|
|
33 | (108) |
|
1 Fearing new dangers: phobias and the cognitive complexity of human emotions |
|
|
35 | (30) |
|
|
|
|
36 | (6) |
|
|
42 | (4) |
|
1.3 Snakes and spiders vs syringes and guns |
|
|
46 | (6) |
|
1.4 Further problems with the evolutionist's explanation of phobias |
|
|
52 | (3) |
|
1.5 An alternative conception of emotion |
|
|
55 | (4) |
|
|
59 | (6) |
|
|
60 | (1) |
|
|
60 | (5) |
|
2 Sexual imprinting and fetishism: an evolutionary hypothesis |
|
|
65 | (26) |
|
|
2.1 The science of fetishism: a history |
|
|
66 | (2) |
|
2.2 The evolution of human sexual preferences |
|
|
68 | (3) |
|
2.3 Sexual imprinting in animals |
|
|
71 | (7) |
|
2.4 Sexual imprinting in humans |
|
|
78 | (4) |
|
2.5 Adaptationism and sexual imprinting |
|
|
82 | (2) |
|
|
84 | (7) |
|
|
86 | (1) |
|
|
86 | (5) |
|
3 Developmental disorders and cognitive architecture |
|
|
91 | (26) |
|
|
3.1 Psychopathologies and cognitive architecture |
|
|
93 | (5) |
|
3.2 Why developmental psychopathologies provide no evidence for modularity |
|
|
98 | (7) |
|
3.3 The epistemology of developmental dissociations |
|
|
105 | (4) |
|
3.4 Evaluation of the strong reading of Premise 2 |
|
|
109 | (3) |
|
|
112 | (5) |
|
|
113 | (4) |
|
4 On the role of ethology in clinical psychiatry: what do ontogenetic and causal factors tell us about ultimate explanations of depression? |
|
|
117 | (24) |
|
|
|
|
117 | (4) |
|
4.2 Ontogenetic processes: early attachment relationships, parental rearing styles, and their relationship with depression |
|
|
121 | (1) |
|
4.3 The ethological analysis of deviant behavior |
|
|
122 | (2) |
|
4.4 Association between observable behavior and depression |
|
|
124 | (4) |
|
4.5 Disturbed interpersonal behavior as a possible causal factor in depression |
|
|
128 | (3) |
|
4.6 Are causal factors of depression linked to adverse early experiences? |
|
|
131 | (1) |
|
4.7 Possible evolutionary explanations of depression |
|
|
132 | (1) |
|
4.8 Discussion: why psychiatry needs ethology |
|
|
133 | (8) |
|
|
136 | (5) |
|
Part 2 Evolutionary theory and the concept of mental disorder |
|
|
141 | (98) |
|
5 Darwin, functional explanation, and the philosophy of psychiatry |
|
|
143 | (30) |
|
|
5.1 Functional explanation: Aristotle, Lucretius, Darwin |
|
|
144 | (8) |
|
5.2 Culver and Gert on distinct sustaining causes |
|
|
152 | (9) |
|
5.3 The designed-defense objection |
|
|
161 | (4) |
|
5.4 Nordenfelt's critique of evolutionary approaches to disorder |
|
|
165 | (8) |
|
|
171 | (2) |
|
6 Evolutionary foundations for psychiatric diagnosis: making DSM-V valid |
|
|
173 | (25) |
|
|
|
6.1 Diagnosis and its discontents |
|
|
174 | (2) |
|
6.2 From clinical diagnosis to the DSM |
|
|
176 | (3) |
|
6.3 The price of progress |
|
|
179 | (2) |
|
|
181 | (2) |
|
6.5 Evolution and emotions |
|
|
183 | (3) |
|
|
186 | (4) |
|
6.7 The importance of analyzing motivational structure |
|
|
190 | (1) |
|
6.8 Towards an evolutionary foundation for psychiatric nosology |
|
|
191 | (7) |
|
|
194 | (4) |
|
7 Normality, disorder, and evolved function: the case of depression |
|
|
198 | (18) |
|
|
|
199 | (1) |
|
7.2 Inductive evidence for a categorical depression/normality distinction |
|
|
200 | (3) |
|
7.3 Evolved functions, dysfunctions, and depression |
|
|
203 | (5) |
|
7.4 The challenge of individual variation |
|
|
208 | (2) |
|
7.5 Disorder versus complaint as the basis for identifying depression |
|
|
210 | (3) |
|
|
213 | (3) |
|
|
213 | (3) |
|
8 Function, dysfunction, and adaptation? |
|
|
216 | (23) |
|
|
|
|
217 | (1) |
|
|
217 | (2) |
|
|
219 | (9) |
|
|
228 | (3) |
|
8.5 Dysfunction and the role of science |
|
|
231 | (4) |
|
|
235 | (4) |
|
|
236 | (1) |
|
|
236 | (3) |
|
Part 3 Psychopathology, evolution, and human nature |
|
|
239 | (70) |
|
9 Mirroring the mind: on empathy and autism |
|
|
241 | (23) |
|
|
|
|
241 | (4) |
|
9.2 Autism spectrum conditions: a lack of "mirroring" and empathy |
|
|
245 | (3) |
|
9.3 The genetics of autism spectrum conditions |
|
|
248 | (4) |
|
9.4 Evolution of autistic traits: low empathy |
|
|
252 | (6) |
|
|
258 | (6) |
|
|
259 | (1) |
|
|
259 | (5) |
|
10 The role of mood change in defining relationships: a tribute to Gregory Bateson (1904-1980) |
|
|
264 | (25) |
|
|
|
264 | (2) |
|
10.2 The overthrown tyrant: a clinical case illustration |
|
|
266 | (2) |
|
10.3 Darwin, Huxley, and sexual selection |
|
|
268 | (2) |
|
10.4 Ritual agonistic behavior and ritual losing |
|
|
270 | (2) |
|
10.5 A triune mind in a triune brain |
|
|
272 | (4) |
|
10.6 Gregory Bateson: defining the relationship |
|
|
276 | (5) |
|
|
281 | (8) |
|
|
283 | (3) |
|
|
286 | (3) |
|
11 From "evolved interpersonal relatedness" to "costly social alienation:" an evolutionary neurophilosophy of schizophrenia |
|
|
289 | (20) |
|
|
|
289 | (3) |
|
11.2 A philosophy of embodiment |
|
|
292 | (2) |
|
11.3 The evolution and development of the social brain |
|
|
294 | (4) |
|
11.4 Schizophrenia and the evolutionary paradigm |
|
|
298 | (1) |
|
11.5 "Interpersonal alienation" from the social world |
|
|
299 | (2) |
|
11.6 Schizophrenia as a social brain disorder |
|
|
301 | (1) |
|
11.7 Resolving the "schizophrenia problem" in evolutionary terms |
|
|
302 | (7) |
|
|
304 | (5) |
Index |
|
309 | |