|
|
x | |
Preface |
|
xi | |
Acknowledgements |
|
xiii | |
|
Introductory survey of the interpretations: some historical background |
|
|
1 | (13) |
|
Introductory survey of the interpretations |
|
|
1 | (2) |
|
Origins and development of probability theory (c. 1650 to c. 1800): mathematics |
|
|
3 | (5) |
|
Origins and development of probability theory (c. 1650 to c. 1800): practical applications and philosophy |
|
|
8 | (6) |
|
|
14 | (11) |
|
Universal determinism and Laplace's demon |
|
|
14 | (3) |
|
|
17 | (1) |
|
|
18 | (4) |
|
Why was probability theory not developed in the Ancient World? |
|
|
22 | (3) |
|
|
25 | (25) |
|
Cambridge in the Edwardian era |
|
|
25 | (4) |
|
Probability as a logical relation |
|
|
29 | (4) |
|
Measurable and non-measurable probabilities: the Principle of Indifference |
|
|
33 | (4) |
|
Paradoxes of the Principle of Indifference |
|
|
37 | (5) |
|
Possible solutions to the paradoxes |
|
|
42 | (8) |
|
|
50 | (38) |
|
Ramsey's criticisms of Keynes |
|
|
52 | (1) |
|
Subjective foundations for mathematical probability: the Ramsey-De Finetti theorem |
|
|
53 | (12) |
|
A comparison of the axiom system given here with the Kolmogorov axioms |
|
|
65 | (4) |
|
Apparently objective probabilities in the subjective theory: exchangeability |
|
|
69 | (6) |
|
The relation between independence and exchangeability |
|
|
75 | (2) |
|
Criticism of De Finetti's exchangeability reduction |
|
|
77 | (6) |
|
Some objections to Bayesianism |
|
|
83 | (2) |
|
De Finetti's route to subjective probability |
|
|
85 | (3) |
|
|
88 | (25) |
|
Probability theory as a science |
|
|
88 | (4) |
|
The empirical laws of probability |
|
|
92 | (4) |
|
The limiting frequency definition of probability |
|
|
96 | (9) |
|
The problem of randomness |
|
|
105 | (4) |
|
The relation between Von Mises' axioms and the Kolmogorov axioms |
|
|
109 | (4) |
|
The propensity theory: (I) general survey |
|
|
113 | (24) |
|
Popper's introduction of the propensity theory |
|
|
114 | (5) |
|
Can there be objective probabilities of single events? |
|
|
119 | (6) |
|
Classification of propensity theories |
|
|
125 | (1) |
|
The propensity theories of Miller, the later Popper and Fetzer |
|
|
126 | (3) |
|
Propensity and causality: Humphreys' paradox |
|
|
129 | (8) |
|
The propensity theory: (II) development of a particular version |
|
|
137 | (32) |
|
Criticisms of operationalism: a non-operationalist theory of conceptual innovation in the natural sciences |
|
|
138 | (7) |
|
A falsifying rule for probability statements |
|
|
145 | (5) |
|
Derivation of the empirical laws of probability |
|
|
150 | (10) |
|
The Kolmogorov axioms and the propensity theory |
|
|
160 | (9) |
|
Intersubjective probability and pluralist views of probability |
|
|
169 | (18) |
|
Intersubjective probability |
|
|
169 | (6) |
|
The spectrum from subjective to objective |
|
|
175 | (5) |
|
Pluralist views of probability |
|
|
180 | (7) |
|
An example of pluralism: differences between the natural and social sciences |
|
|
187 | (19) |
|
General arguments for interpreting probabilities in economics as epistemological rather than objective |
|
|
188 | (7) |
|
Soros on the difference between the natural and social sciences |
|
|
195 | (5) |
|
Operationalism is appropriate for the social sciences, but not for the natural sciences |
|
|
200 | (6) |
Notes |
|
206 | (6) |
References |
|
212 | (6) |
Index |
|
218 | |