Preface |
|
xii | |
Acknowledgements |
|
xviii | |
|
1 Introduction: what is philosophy of psychiatry and why does it matter? |
|
|
1 | (10) |
|
|
1 | (2) |
|
1.2 Psychiatry broadly construed |
|
|
3 | (3) |
|
1.3 Why does the philosophy of psychiatry matter? |
|
|
6 | (5) |
|
1.3.1 It improves understanding and treatment of mental illness |
|
|
6 | (1) |
|
1.3.2 It improves the way our institutions function |
|
|
7 | (1) |
|
1.3.3 It improves our societal responses to mental illness |
|
|
8 | (1) |
|
1.3.4 It gets to the heart of what makes us human |
|
|
9 | (1) |
|
|
10 | (1) |
|
|
10 | (1) |
|
|
10 | (1) |
|
PART 1 Philosophy of Psychiatric Practice and Research |
|
|
11 | (128) |
|
2 What is mental illness? |
|
|
13 | (26) |
|
2.1 Illness, disease and neighbouring notions |
|
|
14 | (7) |
|
2.1.1 Illness, disease, disorder and sickness |
|
|
14 | (4) |
|
2.1.2 Illness versus disability |
|
|
18 | (2) |
|
2.1.3 Illness, difference and diversity |
|
|
20 | (1) |
|
2.2 Philosophical accounts of illness |
|
|
21 | (11) |
|
2.2.1 Mapping the terrain |
|
|
21 | (5) |
|
2.2.2 How viable is objectivism? |
|
|
26 | (2) |
|
|
28 | (1) |
|
2.2.4 Values-based accounts |
|
|
29 | (3) |
|
2.3 Is mental illness a myth? |
|
|
32 | (7) |
|
2.3.1 Szasz's argument against the existence of mental illness |
|
|
33 | (2) |
|
2.3.2 What does the myth achieve? |
|
|
35 | (1) |
|
2.3.3 Taking stock: is mental illness real? |
|
|
36 | (1) |
|
|
37 | (1) |
|
|
38 | (1) |
|
|
38 | (1) |
|
3 Psychiatric diagnosis and the medical model |
|
|
39 | (29) |
|
3.1 Diagnosis and the medical model |
|
|
39 | (8) |
|
3.1.1 The relationship between diagnosis and the medical model |
|
|
40 | (1) |
|
3.1.2 Motivations for the medical model |
|
|
41 | (2) |
|
|
43 | (2) |
|
3.1.4 Current practices of Western psychiatric diagnosis: the DSM and the ICD |
|
|
45 | (1) |
|
3.1.5 Strong versus minimal medical models |
|
|
46 | (1) |
|
3.2 Issues in psychiatric diagnosis |
|
|
47 | (8) |
|
3.2.1 Causalism versus descriptivism |
|
|
48 | (1) |
|
3.2.2 Essentialism versus pragmatism |
|
|
49 | (1) |
|
3.2.3 Objectivism versus evaluativism |
|
|
50 | (1) |
|
3.2.4 Internalism versus externalism |
|
|
50 | (2) |
|
3.2.5 Categories versus dimensions |
|
|
52 | (3) |
|
|
55 | (1) |
|
3.3 Challenges and alternatives to diagnosis |
|
|
55 | (13) |
|
3.3.1 Concerns about the impact of psychiatric diagnosis |
|
|
55 | (2) |
|
3.3.2 Theoretical concerns with diagnosis |
|
|
57 | (3) |
|
3.3.3 Alternatives to diagnosis |
|
|
60 | (5) |
|
3.3.4 To diagnose or not to diagnose? |
|
|
65 | (1) |
|
|
66 | (1) |
|
|
67 | (1) |
|
4 Mental illness, moral responsibility and the boundaries of the person |
|
|
68 | (26) |
|
4.1 Introducing the issue |
|
|
68 | (8) |
|
4.1.1 Responsibility and related notions |
|
|
69 | (2) |
|
4.1.2 A variety of concrete examples |
|
|
71 | (5) |
|
4.2 Approaches to mental illness and moral responsibility |
|
|
76 | (3) |
|
4.2.1 Mental illness and legal responsibility: "the insanity defence" |
|
|
76 | (2) |
|
4.2.2 Incidental versus intrinsic accounts |
|
|
78 | (1) |
|
4.3 Requirements for responsibility |
|
|
79 | (7) |
|
4.3.1 A simple view: information and control |
|
|
80 | (1) |
|
|
80 | (3) |
|
4.3.3 The Sane Deep Self View |
|
|
83 | (2) |
|
|
85 | (1) |
|
4.4 Mental illness revisited |
|
|
86 | (8) |
|
4.4.1 Objectivism and the incidental view |
|
|
86 | (1) |
|
4.4.2 Values-based accounts and the intrinsic view |
|
|
87 | (1) |
|
4.4.3 Fictionalism about mental illness and morality |
|
|
88 | (1) |
|
4.4.4 Narratives of illness, responsibility and personhood |
|
|
89 | (3) |
|
|
92 | (1) |
|
|
92 | (1) |
|
|
93 | (1) |
|
5 Religion, culture and pathology |
|
|
94 | (19) |
|
5.1 The controversial exemption of religious belief |
|
|
95 | (1) |
|
|
96 | (5) |
|
5.2.1 Epistemic considerations for widely held belief |
|
|
97 | (2) |
|
5.2.2 Practical considerations for widely held belief |
|
|
99 | (1) |
|
5.2.3 Biomedical considerations for widely held belief |
|
|
99 | (1) |
|
5.2.4 Taking stock: the intelligence of the masses? |
|
|
100 | (1) |
|
|
101 | (4) |
|
5.3.1 A values-based approach: religion as life-enhancing |
|
|
102 | (1) |
|
5.3.2 An objectivist approach: the cognitive science of religion |
|
|
103 | (2) |
|
5.4 The challenge of cultural sensitivity |
|
|
105 | (8) |
|
5.4.1 An objectivist approach |
|
|
106 | (1) |
|
5.4.2 A values-based approach |
|
|
107 | (1) |
|
5.4.3 The social kindling hypothesis |
|
|
108 | (1) |
|
5.4.4 Context of formation versus context of evaluation |
|
|
109 | (2) |
|
|
111 | (1) |
|
|
112 | (1) |
|
6 Scientific explanation in psychiatry |
|
|
113 | (26) |
|
6.1 The challenge of scientific psychiatry |
|
|
114 | (1) |
|
6.2 The nature of explanation |
|
|
115 | (9) |
|
6.2.1 The formal-logical view |
|
|
116 | (2) |
|
6.2.2 The ontological view |
|
|
118 | (1) |
|
|
119 | (4) |
|
|
123 | (1) |
|
6.3 Levels and kinds of explanation |
|
|
124 | (9) |
|
6.3.1 Levels of explanation: an ambiguity |
|
|
125 | (2) |
|
6.3.2 Levels and kinds of explanation: two separate constraints |
|
|
127 | (2) |
|
6.3.3 A comment on personal explanation |
|
|
129 | (2) |
|
|
131 | (2) |
|
|
133 | (6) |
|
6.4.1 Accuracy and explanatory power |
|
|
133 | (2) |
|
6.4.2 Two kinds of reductionism |
|
|
135 | (2) |
|
|
137 | (1) |
|
|
137 | (1) |
|
|
138 | (1) |
|
PART 2 Philosophy and Psychopathology |
|
|
139 | (186) |
|
|
141 | (34) |
|
7.1 The concept of schizophrenia |
|
|
142 | (3) |
|
7.1.1 A brief history of "schizophrenia" |
|
|
142 | (1) |
|
|
143 | (1) |
|
7.1.3 The relationship between schizophrenia and psychosis |
|
|
144 | (1) |
|
7.2 The phenomenon itself |
|
|
145 | (3) |
|
7.2.1 Diagnosing schizophrenia |
|
|
146 | (1) |
|
7.2.2 Epidemiology of schizophrenia |
|
|
147 | (1) |
|
|
148 | (14) |
|
7.3.1 Source-monitoring accounts |
|
|
149 | (2) |
|
7.3.2 Self-monitoring accounts |
|
|
151 | (3) |
|
7.3.3 The dopamine hypothesis |
|
|
154 | (1) |
|
7.3.4 Introducing the predictive processing framework |
|
|
155 | (4) |
|
7.3.5 Predictive processing accounts of psychosis |
|
|
159 | (3) |
|
7.4 Phenomenological approaches |
|
|
162 | (4) |
|
7.4.1 Big P versus Little p phenomenology |
|
|
162 | (1) |
|
7.4.2 Ipseity accounts of schizophrenia |
|
|
163 | (1) |
|
7.4.3 Psychosis as disruption to the anticipatory structure of experience |
|
|
164 | (1) |
|
7.4.4 The explanatory contribution of phenomenological approaches |
|
|
165 | (1) |
|
7.5 The case against schizophrenia |
|
|
166 | (9) |
|
7.5.1 Socio-political critiques |
|
|
167 | (1) |
|
7.5.2 Scientific critiques |
|
|
168 | (1) |
|
7.5.3 Pragmatic critiques |
|
|
169 | (1) |
|
7.5.4 Where does this leave us? |
|
|
170 | (2) |
|
|
172 | (1) |
|
|
173 | (1) |
|
|
173 | (2) |
|
|
175 | (27) |
|
8.1 The varieties of voice hearing |
|
|
176 | (4) |
|
8.1.1 Varieties in context |
|
|
176 | (1) |
|
8.1.2 Varieties in phenomenology |
|
|
177 | (3) |
|
8.1.3 Varieties of underlying mechanism |
|
|
180 | (1) |
|
8.2 The self-monitoring account |
|
|
180 | (10) |
|
8.2.1 Introducing self-monitoring |
|
|
181 | (1) |
|
8.2.2 Inner speech-based self-monitoring accounts |
|
|
181 | (2) |
|
8.2.3 Arguments in favour of inner speech-based self-monitoring accounts |
|
|
183 | (2) |
|
8.2.4 Problems and further developments |
|
|
185 | (5) |
|
8.2.5 Self-monitoring without inner speech? |
|
|
190 | (1) |
|
|
190 | (5) |
|
8.3.1 Spontaneous activation accounts |
|
|
191 | (1) |
|
8.3.2 Memory-based accounts |
|
|
192 | (2) |
|
8.3.3 Social deafferentation accounts |
|
|
194 | (1) |
|
|
195 | (1) |
|
8.4 From self-monitoring to predictive processing |
|
|
195 | (7) |
|
8.4.1 The problem of hypervigilance hallucinations |
|
|
195 | (1) |
|
8.4.2 Prediction is pervasive in all cognition, not just action monitoring |
|
|
196 | (1) |
|
8.4.3 A predictive processing account of AVH |
|
|
197 | (3) |
|
8.4.4 Remaining challenges and future directions |
|
|
200 | (1) |
|
|
200 | (1) |
|
|
201 | (1) |
|
|
201 | (1) |
|
|
202 | (36) |
|
9.1 The concept of delusion |
|
|
203 | (9) |
|
9.1.1 Delusion as a diagnostically important psychiatric concept |
|
|
203 | (3) |
|
9.1.2 Delusions as epistemically defective mental states |
|
|
206 | (4) |
|
9.1.3 A change of approach |
|
|
210 | (2) |
|
9.2 Examples of clinical delusions |
|
|
212 | (6) |
|
9.2.1 Schizophrenia spectrum and other psychotic disorders |
|
|
212 | (1) |
|
9.2.2 Delusions and mood disorders |
|
|
213 | (1) |
|
9.2.3 Delusion and brain injury |
|
|
214 | (3) |
|
9.2.4 Taking stock: taxonomies of delusion |
|
|
217 | (1) |
|
9.3 Explanatory accounts of delusion |
|
|
218 | (10) |
|
9.3.1 Delusions in psychotic disorders |
|
|
218 | (1) |
|
9.3.2 The classic bottom-up account of Capgras delusion (Ellis and Young 1990) |
|
|
219 | (2) |
|
9.3.3 Explanationist versus endorsement models |
|
|
221 | (2) |
|
9.3.4 One-factor versus two-factor accounts |
|
|
223 | (2) |
|
9.3.5 An alternative approach: top-down accounts |
|
|
225 | (1) |
|
|
226 | (2) |
|
|
228 | (10) |
|
9.4.1 Why might (some) delusions not be beliefs? |
|
|
228 | (2) |
|
|
230 | (2) |
|
9.4.3 So do delusional patients fail to be believers? |
|
|
232 | (2) |
|
|
234 | (1) |
|
|
235 | (1) |
|
|
236 | (2) |
|
|
238 | (24) |
|
10.1 Introducing depression |
|
|
239 | (4) |
|
10.1.1 Depression in the DSM |
|
|
239 | (2) |
|
10.1.2 The phenomenology of depression |
|
|
241 | (1) |
|
10.1.3 Who gets depressed? |
|
|
242 | (1) |
|
10.2 Delineating depression |
|
|
243 | (9) |
|
10.2.1 Is depression an extreme version of something familiar? |
|
|
244 | (2) |
|
10.2.2 How do we distinguish pathological depression from "healthy" sadness? |
|
|
246 | (1) |
|
10.2.3 Depression and dysthymia |
|
|
247 | (3) |
|
10.2.4 Depression, melancholia and cross-cultural variation |
|
|
250 | (2) |
|
10.3 Explaining depression |
|
|
252 | (10) |
|
10.3.1 Phenomenological explanations |
|
|
252 | (1) |
|
10.3.2 Neuroscientific and cognitive approaches |
|
|
253 | (2) |
|
10.3.3 Predictive processing accounts |
|
|
255 | (1) |
|
10.3.4 Depression and motivation |
|
|
256 | (4) |
|
|
260 | (1) |
|
|
261 | (1) |
|
|
261 | (1) |
|
|
262 | (27) |
|
11.1 Introducing addiction |
|
|
262 | (2) |
|
|
264 | (13) |
|
11.2.1 The Lay View of addiction |
|
|
265 | (3) |
|
11.2.2 Addiction as a brain disease |
|
|
268 | (3) |
|
11.2.3 Addiction as a mental illness |
|
|
271 | (1) |
|
11.2.4 Addiction and self-control |
|
|
272 | (4) |
|
11.2.5 A socio-pragmatic account |
|
|
276 | (1) |
|
11.3 The science of addiction |
|
|
277 | (5) |
|
11.3.1 Addiction as evolutionary mismatch |
|
|
277 | (1) |
|
11.3.2 Addiction as dysfunctional reward learning |
|
|
278 | (1) |
|
11.3.3 Addiction as incentive salience |
|
|
279 | (1) |
|
11.3.3 Predictive processing accounts |
|
|
280 | (2) |
|
11.4 Remaining philosophical issues |
|
|
282 | (7) |
|
11.4.1 Addiction and rationality |
|
|
282 | (1) |
|
11.4.2 Addiction, responsibility and blame |
|
|
283 | (2) |
|
11.4.3 Addiction and pathology |
|
|
285 | (2) |
|
|
287 | (1) |
|
|
287 | (1) |
|
|
288 | (1) |
|
12 The future of philosophy of psychiatry |
|
|
289 | (36) |
|
12.1 Overlooked phenomena |
|
|
290 | (5) |
|
12.1.1 Post-traumatic stress disorder |
|
|
290 | (1) |
|
|
291 | (1) |
|
12.1.3 Personality disorders |
|
|
292 | (3) |
|
12.2 Mental well-being in a digital world |
|
|
295 | (2) |
|
12.2.1 The self and self-esteem online |
|
|
295 | (1) |
|
12.2.2 Loneliness and togetherness online |
|
|
295 | (1) |
|
12.2.3 Internet addiction |
|
|
296 | (1) |
|
12.3 The rise of computational psychiatry |
|
|
297 | (2) |
|
12.3.1 Clinical computational neuroscience |
|
|
297 | (1) |
|
12.3.2 Computational psychiatric epidemiology |
|
|
298 | (1) |
|
12.3.3 Deep learning in diagnostics and early intervention |
|
|
298 | (1) |
|
12.4 Externalistic psychiatry |
|
|
299 | (2) |
|
12.4.1 Embodied psychiatry |
|
|
300 | (1) |
|
12.4.2 Embedded psychiatry |
|
|
300 | (1) |
|
12.4.3 Extended psychiatry |
|
|
301 | (1) |
|
12.4.4 Enactive psychiatry |
|
|
301 | (1) |
|
12.4.5 Clinical consequences of externalistic psychiatry |
|
|
301 | (1) |
|
12.5 Understanding psychiatric discourse |
|
|
301 | (24) |
|
12.5.1 Beyond realism and anti-realism: expressivism, fictionalism, constructivism |
|
|
302 | (1) |
|
12.5.2 The ameliorativist agenda: optimising discourse for scientific progress and social justice |
|
|
303 | (1) |
|
|
304 | (1) |
|
|
304 | (1) |
|
|
305 | (20) |
Index |
|
325 | |